The Frankfurt
School of German Social Theory has exerted a considerable influence over the
sociology of the last two generations. Originally a centre for the study of
Marxist theory brought into being in the first years of Weimar Republic
Germany, the work of its principal figures has nonetheless always had a
somewhat ambiguous relationship with mainstream Western Marxism, right through
from the early writings of Max
Horkheimer in the 1930s to the very recent work of Jรผrgen Habermas.
However, the development of a distinct ‘critical theory’ of society by Horkheimer and Adorno and its reworking
by later Frankfurt theorists constituted a (sometimes tenuous) thread of ideas
and concepts which gave the Frankfurt School an important role in the expansion
of modern sociology. Despite the
somewhat paradoxical rejection of Marxist concepts by many Frankfurt School
writers, it was especially instrumental in the renaissance of Marxist sociology
which took hold in the late 1960s.
As Tom Bottomore makes clear in drawing this parallel,
the Frankfurt School thinkers were led by their pessimism into a retreat from
Marxian social theory, and then towards an essentially philosophical and
neo-Hegelian critique of ideology. Perhaps best seen as ‘radicals in despair’, Horkheimer, Marcuse and Adorno were
responsible for a theory of capitalist society which emphasized its cultural
manifestations above all other aspects. Caught in a climate of cultural loss
and decline which must be linked to their experience of the rise of Fascism in
Germany, the ‘critical theory’ developed by these men during this period was
overwhelmingly concerned with the mounting irrationality of social and cultural
values, and their reflection in the ideas of positivism and ‘scientism’.
Herbert Marcuse’s
version of ‘critical theory’
shares many of these aspects of Ideologiekritik conducted not from empirical
observation but philosophical speculation. His One-Dimensional Man (certainly
his best known work) thus remains firmly within the contemplative cast of
Frankfurt School work, its nature as a philosophical critique of advanced
capitalism perhaps explaining why its great popularity did not lead to any
significant attempts at extension or empirical demonstration of the thesis
which it contains.
The Frankfurt
School is a complex phenomenon, and the style of social thought which has come to be
principally associated with it—‘critical theory’—has been expounded and
interpreted in a variety of ways. The institutional basis upon which the school
developed was the Institute of Social Research, officially established on 3
February 1923 by a decree of the Ministry of Education, and affiliated with the
University of Frankfurt.
The founding of
the Institute took place in
the particular conditions produced by the victory of the Bolshevik revolution
in Russia and the defeat of the Central European revolutions, notably that in
Germany; and it can be seen as one response to the need felt by left wing
intellectuals to reappraise Marxist theory, and especially the relation between
theory and practice, in the new circumstances.
In this sense the
Institute formed part of a
wider movement of thought which has come to be known as ‘Western Marxism’,
characterized on one side by diverse, predominantly philosophical and Hegelian
reinterpretations of Marxist theory in relation to the advanced capitalist
societies, and on the other, by an increasingly critical view of the
development of society and the state in the USSR.
The Formation of
the School
Horkheimer, in
the address delivered on the occasion of his official installation as director of the Institute
in January 1931, indicated clearly, while paying tribute to the work of his
predecessor, that the Institute was about to take a new direction. ‘Social
philosophy’ now emerged as its main preoccupation; not in the sense of a
philosophical theory of value which would provide a superior insight into the
meaning of social life, nor as some kind of synthesis of the results of the
specialized social sciences, but rather as the source of important questions to
be investigated by these sciences and as a framework in which ‘the universal
would not be lost sight of’. In subsequent essays of the 1930s Horkheimer
developed his conception of the role of philosophy primarily through a
criticism of modern positivism or empiricism (the terms are used
interchangeably), and in particular that of the Vienna Circle. His argument in
one important essay, ‘The latest attack on metaphysics’ (1937), proceeds on two
levels.
Horkheimer
pursued this argument
in his best known essay of the 1930s, ‘Traditional
and critical theory’ (1937), which should perhaps be regarded as the founding document, or charter, of the
Frankfurt School. ‘Traditional theory’ is there interpreted as the implicit
or explicit outlook of the modern natural sciences, expressed in modern
philosophy as positivism/empiricism; and Horkheimer is above all concerned with
the diffusion of this conception of theory in the ‘sciences of man and society
[which] have attempted to follow the lead of the natural sciences’. The opposed
kind of social thought, ‘critical theory’, rejects the procedure of determining
objective facts with the aid of conceptual systems, from a purely external standpoint,
and claims that ‘the facts, as they emerge from the work of society, are not
extrinsic in the same degree as they are for the savant…critical thinking…is
motivated today by the effort really to transcend the tension and to abolish
the opposition between the individual’s purposefulness, spontaneity, and
rationality, and those work-process relationships on which society is built’.
But how, in that case, is critical thought related to experience? Is it
anything more than ‘conceptual poetry’ or an ‘impotent expression of states of
mind’? Marx and Engels had grounded their critical theory in the situation of
the proletariat, which necessarily struggles for emancipation.
Adorno’s
contribution to the formation of a school of critical theory is much more ambiguous and obscure.
Until 1938 his relations with the Institute were informal, and his principal
interests lay in the field of culture (particularly music), psychoanalysis, and
aesthetic theory (where he was profoundly influenced by Walter Benjamin). The
philosophical outlook which he developed during this time was not a ‘dialetical
social theory’, but what he later called ‘negative dialectics’; that is, a
criticism of all philosophical positions and social theories. This appears to
be a form of relativism or scepticism, which denies the possibility of any
absolute starting point (‘identity principle’) or ultimate basis for human
thought, though Adorno attempted to evade this outcome. At all events his
philosophical stance is very different from that of Horkheimer or Marcuse, both
of whom tried to formulate a positive social theory on the basis of a Hegelian
concept of ‘reason’. Adorno was also much more remote from Marxism than his
colleagues. In his inaugural lecture at the University of Frankfurt, ‘The
actuality of philosophy’ (1931), he expounded a view of philosophy which
claimed to be both ‘dialectical’ and ‘materialist’, but as Buck-Morss comments
‘…it was not dialectical materialism in any orthodox sense…throughout his life
he differed fundamentally from Marx in that his philosophy never included a
theory of political action’. Moreover, unlike Horkheimer and Marcuse, who only
gradually abandoned their (qualified) belief in the revolutionary potential of
the working class, Adorno seems never to have given any serious attention to
Marx’s economic analysis or his theory of class, and he rejected entirely the
idea of a theory of history, or ‘science of history’, which is one of the
fundamental elements in Marx’s thought.
During its formative period, and still more in its
later phases, the Frankfurt School detached itself increasingly from Marx’s
theory and from classical Marxism, abandoning large (and crucial) parts of that
theory, but without embarking upon a systematic critical confrontation with it.
For more on the Frankfurt School of German Social
Theory, kindly read -
Tom Bottomore’s The Frankfurt School and its Critics
published by Routledge [Special Indian Edition]
No comments:
Post a Comment